Categories
Business Cycles Columbia Economists Methodology

Columbia. Wesley Clair Mitchell Reflects on his Personal Research Style. 1928

This post provides a transcription of Wesley Clair Mitchell’s original reply to methodological questions posed to him by his younger Columbia colleague John Maurice Clark in 1928. Clark was so impressed with Mitchell’s reply that he had it published in 1931 and later then reprinted in 1952 (see links below). For autobiographical context I have included a brief statement by Mitchell, one of Decatur, Illinois’ favorite sons, that was written shortly after his methodological reflections.

Fun Fact: Adolph C. Miller, who was one of Mitchell’s teachers at the University of Chicago and later his colleague at Berkeley, was married to Mary Sprague, older sister of Mitchell’s wife, Lucy Sprague.

Coming attraction: We will learn more about Wesley Clair Mitchell’s parents and the Baptist grand-aunt who raised his mother in a later post.

______________________

Decatur Herald (Decatur, Illinois)
7 July 1929, p. 44

Mitchell One of First To Prove Business Cycle

Every business man in the United States is familiar now with the theory of the business cycle. Comparatively few, even in Decatur, probably know that it was a former Decaturian, Dr Wesley C. Mitchell, who did the pioneer work in economic research establishing the theory of a business cycle.

“My father and mother were John Wesley Mitchell and L. Medora McClellan Mitchell.

“After living several years opposite the Stapps Chapel, we moved out to a ten-acre place on what later became Leafland avenue. There were seven children and we all went through Decatur schools. My High school class was 1893; but I dropped out in the fourth year in order to push more rapidly my preparation for taking college entrance examinations. In that way I entered the University of Chicago in the autumn of ’93. From that time forward I returned to Decatur only during vacations until the time when my parents moved to Louisiana about 1902.

Studied In Germany

“My undergraduate work was done at the University of Chicago. Graduating in 1896, I received a fellowship which permitted me to go on immediately with postgraduate work. The year ’97-98 I spent on a traveling fellowship in Germany and Austria. The next year I was back at Chicago receiving the degree of Doctor of Philosophy summa cum laude in ’99. My chief subjects were economics and philosophy.

“No more congenial opening turning up, I spent 1900 in the Census Office at Washington in a small Division of Analysis and Research presided over by Walter F. Willcox of Cornell. Next year I was appointed instructor at the University of Chicago and taught there in 1900-02. The end of this period I published my first book, “A History of the Greenbacks.”

“One of my teachers at Chicago, Professor A. C. Miller, now a member of the Federal Reserve board, was called to the University of California as head of the Department of Economics. He asked me to go with him. As a result I lived from 1902 to 1912 in Berkeley as an assistant, associate and finally full professor of economics. While there I published a second volume of my monetary studies called “Gold Prices and Wages in the United States”(1908), and also a book called “Business Cycles” (1913). I also spent one of these years lecturing at Harvard.

Helped to Launch School

“In 1912 I married Lucy Sprague a daughter of Otho S. A. Sprague of Chicago. We went to Europe for a year and then came to live in New York city where I became attached to Columbia University. During the war I was chief of the Price Section in the Division of Planning and Statistics in the War Industries board. After the war I helped organize the New School for Social Research in New York and later the National Bureau of Economic Research, with which I am still connected as one of the directors.

“In these later years my investigations have been carried on very largely in conjunction with the National Bureau’s programs. My latest book, “Business Cycles: The Problem and Its Setting,” was published in 1927, and I am now working upon the supplementary volume to be called “Business Cycles: The Rhythm of Business Activity.”

“It is many years since I have been in Decatur or had an opportunity to talk with any of my old friends, aside from Will Westerman who graduated from the Decatur High school a little before my time, and who is now one of my colleagues at Columbia, where he is a professor of ancient history.

“It will be a great pleasure to get the records of other old friends which your Centenary number will doubtless contain. Accept my congratulations upon this enterprise.

WESLEY C. MITCHELL

______________________

NBER Memorial Volume
for Wesley Clair Mitchell

Wesley Clair Mitchell: The Economic Scientist, National Bureau of Economic Research, New York, 1952.

______________________

Backstory:

Memorial Address
by John Maurice Clark.

“I had undertaken to analyze his methods of studying business cycles, for a volume of such analyses, edited by Stuart Rice; and as part of my preparations I had written to Mitchell, asking him some rather searching questions. In reply, he sent me an autobiographical sketch of his intellectual development, starting with his adolescent arguments over theology with his grandaunt. The letter was close to three thousand words long and so beautifully written as to be fit for publication without the change of a comma. Much against his desires, Mitchell was persuaded to allow this correspondence to be published, as part of the study which had occasioned it.* Its great value, naturally, lay in the fact that it had been written without a thought of publication, merely in a characteristically generous response to my request for inside information. More than anything else I know in print, it gives not only his typical mental attitudes, but the flavor of his genially pungent personality.”

Source: Wesley Clair Mitchell: The Economic Scientist, National Bureau of Economic Research (New York, 1952), p. 142.

*Appendix: “The Author’s Own Account of His Methodological Interests” to John Maurice Clark’s “Preface to Social Economics” in Methods in Social Science: A Case Book. Edited by Stuart A. Rice for the Social Science Research Council, Committee on Scientific Method in the Social Sciences. University of Chicago Press, 1931. Pages 673 ff.

______________________

Typed copy of Wesley Clair Mitchell’s Response to Questions
posed him by John Maurice Clark

[Handwritten note: “Revised Feb 11, 1929”]

Huckleberry Rocks, Greensboro, Vt.
August 9, 1928.

Dear Maurice:

                  I know no reason why you should hesitate to dissect a colleague for the instruction, or amusement, of mankind. Your interest in ideas rather than in personalities will be clear to any intelligent reader. Nor is the admiration I feel for you skill as an analyst likely to grow less warm if you take me apart to see how I work. Indeed, I should like to know myself!

                  Whether I can really help you is doubtful. The questions you put are questions I must answer from rather hazy recollections of what went on inside me thirty and forty and more years ago. Doubtless my present impressions of how I grew up are largely rationalizations. But perhaps you can make something out of the type of rationalizations in which I indulge.

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  Concerning the inclination you note to prefer concrete problems and methods to abstract ones, my hypothesis is that it got started, perhaps manifested itself would be more accurate, in childish theological discussions with my grand aunt. She was the best of Baptists, and knew exactly how the Lord had planned the world. God is love; he planned salvation; he ordained immersion; his immutable word left no doubt about the inevitable fate of those who did not walk in the path he had marked. Hell is no stain upon his honor, no inconsistency with love. — I adored the logic and thought my grand aunt flinched unworthily when she expressed hopes that some back-stairs method might be found of saving from everlasting flame the ninety and nine who are not properly baptized. But I also read the bible and began to cherish private opinions about the character of the potentate in Heaven. Also I observed that his followers on earth did not seem to get what was promised them here and now. I developed an impish delight in dressing up logical difficulties which my grand aunt could not dispose of. She always slipped back into the logical scheme, and blinked the facts in which I came to take a proprietary interest.

                  I suppose there is nothing better as a teething-ring for a child who likes logic than the garden variety of Christian theology. I cut my eye-teeth on it with gusto and had not entirely lost interest in that exercise when I went to college.

                  There I began studying philosophy and economics about the same time. The similarity of the two disciplines struck me at once, I found no difficulty in grasping the differences between the great philosophical systems as they were presented by our text-books and our teachers. Economic theory was easier still. Indeed, I thought the successive systems of economics were rather crude affairs compared with the subtleties of the metaphysicians. Having run the gamut from Plato to T. H. Green (as undergraduates do) I felt the gamut from Quesnay to Marshall was a minor theme. The technical part of the theory was easy. Give me premises and I could spin speculations by the yard. Also I knew that my “deductions” were futile. It seemed to me that people who took seriously the sort of articles which were then appearing in the Q.J.E. might have a better time if they went in for metaphysics proper.

                  Meanwhile I was finding something really interesting in philosophy and in economics. John Dewey was giving courses under all sorts of titles and every one of them dealt with the same problem — how we think. I was fascinated by his view of the place which logic holds in human behavior. It explained the economic theorists. The thing to do was to find out how they came to attack certain problems; why they took certain premises as a matter of course; why they did not consider all the permutations and variants of those problems which were logically possible; why their contemporaries thought their conclusions were significant. And, if one wanted to try his own hand at constructive theorizing, Dewey’s notion pointed the way. It is a misconception to suppose that consumers guide their course by ratiocination — they don’t think except under stress. There is no way of deducing from certain principles what they will do, just because their behavior is not itself rational. One has to find out what they do. That is a matter of observation, which the economic theorists had taken all too lightly. Economic theory became a fascinating subject — the orthodox types particularly — when one began to take the mental operations of the theorists as the problem, instead of taking their theories seriously.

                  Of course Veblen fitted perfectly into this set of notions. What drew me to him was his artistic side. I had a weakness for paradoxes — Hell set up by the God of love. But Veblen was a master developing beautiful subtleties, while I was a tyro emphasizing the obvious. He did have such a good time with the theory of the leisure class and then with the preconceptions of economic theory! And the economists reacted with such bewildered soberness: There was a man who really could play with ideas! If one wanted to indulge in the game of spinning theories who could match his skill and humor? But if anything were needed to convince me that the standard procedure of orthodox economics could meet no scientific tests, it was that Veblen got nothing more certain by his dazzling performances with another set of premises. His working conceptions of human nature might be a vast improvement: he might have uncanny insights; but he could do no more than make certain conclusions plausible — like the rest. How important were the factors he dealt with and the factors he scamped was never established.

                  That was a sort of problem which was beginning to concern me. William Hill set me a course paper on “Wool Growing and the Tariff.” I read a lot of the tariff speeches and got a new sidelight on the uses to which economic theory is adapted, and the ease with which it is brushed aside on occasion. Also I wanted to find out what really had happened to wool growers as a result of protection. The obvious thing to do was to collect and analyze the statistical data. If at the end I had demonstrated no clear-cut conclusion, I at least knew how superficial were the notions of the gentlemen who merely debated the tariff issue, whether in Congress or in academic quarters. That was my first “Investigation” — I did it in the way which seemed obvious, following up the available materials as far as I could, and reporting what I found to be the “facts.” It’s not easy to see how any student assigned this topic could do much with it in any other way.

                  A brief introduction to English economic history by A. C. Miller, and unsystematic readings in anthropology instigated by Veblen reenforced  the impressions I was getting from other sources. Everything Dewey was saying about how we think, and when we think, made these fresh materials significant, and got fresh significance Itself. Men had always deluded themselves, it appeared, with strictly logical accounts of the world and their own origin; they had always fabricated theories for their spiritual comfort and practical guidance which ran far beyond the realm of fact without straining their powers of belief. My grand aunt’s theology; Plato and Quesnay; Kant, Ricardo and Karl Marx; Cairnes and Jevons, even Marshall were much of a piece. Each system was tolerably self-consistent — as if that were a test of “truth”! There were realms in which speculation on the basis of assumed premises achieved real wonders; but they were realms in which one began frankly by cutting loose from the phenomena we can observe. And the results were enormously useful. But that way of thinking seemed to get good results only with reference to the simplest of problems, such as numbers and spatial relations. Yet men practiced this type of thinking with reference to all types of problems which could not be treated readily on a matter-of-fact basis — creation, God, “just” prices in the middle ages, the Wealth of Nations in Adam Smith’s time, the distribution of incomes in Ricardo’s generation, the theory of equilibrium in my own day.

                  There seemed to be one way of making real progress, slow, very slow, but tolerably sure. That was the way of natural science. I really knew nothing of science and had enormous respect for its achievements. Not the Darwinian type of speculation which was then so much in the ascendant — that was another piece of theology. But chemistry and physics. They had been built up not in grand systems like soap bubbles; but by the patient processes of observation and testing — always critical testing — of the relations between the working hypotheses and the processes observed. There was plenty of need for rigorous thinking, indeed of thinking more precise than Ricardo achieved; but the place for it was inside the investigation so to speak — the place that mathematics occuped in physics as an indispensable tool. The problems one could really do something with in economics were problems in which speculation could be controlled.

                  That’s the best account I can give off hand of my predilection for the concrete. Of course it seems to me rather a predilection for problems one can treat with some approach to scientific method. The abstract is to be made use of at every turn, as a handmaiden to help hew the wood and draw the water. I loved romance — particularly William Morris’ tales of lands that never were — and utopias, and economic systems, of which your father’s when I came to know it seemed the most beautiful; but these were objects of art, and I was a workman who wanted to become a scientific worker, who might enjoy the visions which we see in mountain mists but who trusted only what we see in the light of common day.

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  Besides the spice of rationalizing which doubtless vitiates my recollections — uncontrolled recollections at that — this account worries me by the time it is taking yours as well as mine. I’ll try to answer the other questions concisely.

                  Business cycles turned up as a problem in the course of the studies which I began with Laughlin. My first book on the greenbacks dealt only with the years of rapid depreciation and spasmodic wartime reaction. I knew that I had not gotten to the bottom of the problems and wanted to go on, so I compiled that frightful second book as an apparatus for a more thorough analysis. By the time it was finished I had learned to see the problems in a larger way. Veblen’s paper on “Industrial and Pecuniary Employments” had a good deal to do with opening my eyes. Presently I found myself working on the system of prices and its place in modern economic life. Then I got hold of Simmel’s Theorie des Geldes — a fascinating book. But Simmel, no more than Veblen, knew the relative importance of the factors he was working with. My manuscript grew — it lies unpublished to this day. As it grew in size it became more speculative. I was working away from any solid foundation — having a good time, but sliding gayly over abysses I had not explored. One of the most formidable was the recurring readjustments of prices, which economists treated apart from their general theories of value, under the caption “Crises.” I had to look into the problem. It proved to be susceptible of attack by methods which I thought reliable. The result was the big California monograph. I thought of it as an introduction to economic theory.

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  This conception is responsible for the chapter on “Modern Economic Organization.” I don’t remember precisely at what stage the need of such a discussion dawned upon me. But I have to do everything a dozen times. Doubtless I wrote parts of that chapter fairly early and other parts late as I found omissions in the light of the chapters on “The Rhythm of Business Activity.” Of course, I put nothing in which did not seem to me strictly pertinent to the understanding of the processes with which the volume dealt. That I did not cover the field very intelligently, even from my own viewpoint, appears from a comparison of the books published in 1913 and 1927. Doubtless before I am done with my current volume, I shall be passing a similar verdict upon the chapter as I left it last year.

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  As to the relation between my analytic description and “causal” theory I have no clear ideas — though I might develop some at need. To me it seems that I try to follow through the interlacing processes involved in business expansion and contraction by the aid of everything I know, checking my speculations just as far as I can by the data of observation. Among the things I “know” are the way in which economic activity is organized in business enterprises, and the way these enterprises are conducted for money profits. But that is not a simple matter which enables me to deduce certain results — or rather, to deduce results with certainty. There is much in the workings of business technique which I should never think of if I were not always turning back to observation. And I should not trust even my reasoning about what business men will do if I could not check it up. Some unverifiable suggestions do emerge; but I hope it is always clear that they are unverified. Very likely what I try to do is merely carrying out the requirements of John Stuart Mill’s “complete method.” But there is a great deal more passing back and forth between hypotheses and observation, each modifying and enriching the other, than I seem to remember in Mill’s version. Perhaps I do him injustice as a logician through default of memory; but I don’t think I do classical economics injustice when I say that it erred sadly in trying to think out a deductive scheme and then talked of verifying that. Until a science has gotten to the stage of elaborating the details of an established body of theory — say finding a planet from the aberrations of orbits, or filling a gap in the table of elements — it is rash to suppose one can get an hypothesis which stands much chance of holding good except from a process of attempted verification, modification, fresh observation, and so on. (Of course, there is a good deal of commerce between most economic theorizing and personal observation of an irregular sort  — that is what has given our theories their considerable measure of significance. But I must not go off into that issue.)

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  Finally, about the table of decils. One cannot be sure that a given point on the decil curves represents the relative price of just one commodity or the relative wage of just one industry. For it often happens, particularly near the center of the range covered, that several commodities and industries have identical relatives in a certain year and these identical relatives may happen to be decil points. But I think the criticisms you make of my interpretations of the movements of the decils are valid. Frederick C. Mills makes similar strictures in his Behavior of Prices, pp. 279 following, particularly p. 283 note. The fact is that when writing the first book about business cycles I seem to have had no clear ideas about secular trends. The term does not occur in the index. Seasonal variations appear to be mentioned only in connection with interest rates. Of course certain rough notions along these lines may be inferred; but not such definite ideas as would safeguard me against the errors you point out. What makes matters worse for me, I was behind the times in this respect. J.P. Norton’s Statistical Studies in the New York Money Market had come out in 1902, I ought to have known and made use of his work.

                  That is only one of several serious blemishes upon the statistical work in my 1913 volume. After Hourwich left Chicago, and that was before I got deep into economics, no courses were given on statistics in my time. I was blissfully ignorant of everything except the simplest devices. To this day I have remained an awkward amateur, always ready to invent some crude scheme for looking into anything I want to know about, and quite likely to be betrayed by my own apparatus. I shall die in the same sad state.

*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *  *

                  I did not intend to inflict such a screed upon you when I started. Now that I have read it over, I fell compunctions about sending it. Also some hesitations. I don’t like the intellectual arrogances which I developed as a boy, which stuck by me in college, and which I shall never get rid of wholly. My only defense is that I was made on a certain pattern and had to do the best I could — like everybody else. Doubtless I am at bottom as simple a theologian as my grand aunt. The difference is that I have made my view of the world out of the materials which were available in the 1880’s and ’90’s, whereas she built, with less competent help than I had, out of the material available in the farming communities of the 1840’s and ’50’s. Perhaps you have been able to develop an outlook on the world which gives you a juster view than I had of the generations which preceded me and of the generation to which I belong. If I did not think so, I should not be sending you a statement so readily misunderstood.

Ever yours,
Wesley C. Mitchell.
(Copy by J.M.C. )

Source: Columbia University Libraries, Special Manuscript Collections. Mitchell, W.C. Collection. Box C8, Ch-Ec. Folder “Clark, John Maurice v.p., 8 Apr 1926 & 21 Apr 1927 to Wesley C. Mitchell 2 a.l.s. (with related material)”.

Image: Wesley Clair Mitchell.  Detail from a departmental photo dated “early 1930’s” in Columbia University Libraries, Manuscript Collections, Columbiana. Department of Economics Collection, Box 9, Folder “Photos”. Colorized at Economics in the Rear-view Mirror.

Categories
Exam Questions Harvard Methodology

Harvard. Semester Exams for Methods of Economic Investigation. Carver, 1907-1908

The following exam questions on Methods of Economic Investigation were for a course listed as primarily for graduate students, taught by Thomas Nixon Carver at Harvard, 1907-08. It is hard for me to imagine there was any period in the last 120 or so years when anyone might have been impressed by this shallow dive into questions of methodology. Am I missing something?

________________________

Some biographical details
for Thomas N. Carver

https://www.irwincollier.com/harvard-course-readings-final-exams-and-enrollment-for-principles-of-sociology-carver-and-field-1904-1905/

____________________________ 

Exams from earlier years

1900-01
1901-02
1903-04
1904-05

____________________________ 

Course Enrollment
1907-08

Economics 13 hf. Professor Carver. — Methods of Economic Investigation

Total 3: 2 Graduates, 1 Divinity.

Source: Harvard University. Report of the President of Harvard College, 1907-1908, p. 67.

____________________________ 

ECONOMICS 13
Mid-year examination, 1907-08

  1. How can the method of difference be applied to the determination of the shares in the distribution of wealth.
  2. What do you understand by the analytical method in economics? Give examples.
  3. Is the mathematical and diagrammatic method capable of being used in investigation, or it is only a method of exposition? Give reasons for your answer.
  4. Is there a noticeable tendency among certain writers to treat economics as though it were the science of surplus wealth, and among others to treat it as a science of human well-being? What is the real difference between the two points of view.
  5. How would you subdivide economics into departments; (a) if you were going to write a text-book; (b) if you were going to organize a department of economics in a university where you could have a teaching staff, say, of 8 specialists, and could get men who would fit into whatever special fields you might plan for them?

Source: Harvard University Archives. Harvard University. Mid-year Examinations, 1852-1943. Box 8, Bound Volume: Examination Papers, Mid-Years 1907-08.

ECONOMICS 13
Year-end examination, 1907-08

  1. To what extent is the question of method determined by the kind of information which the investigator is seeking? Illustrate.
  2. Is the question of method ever confused with the question of the source from which information must be gathered? Illustrate.
  3. Is the mathematical method a method of investigation or of exposition? Explain and illustrate.
  4. What quantitative concepts are, or should be, used when we speak of a quantity of land, of oats, of capital, of labor, of money?
  5. Describe and criticise three methods of ascertaining to what extent immigration, since 1820, has increased the population of the United States.
  6. Contrast three methods of ascertaining the causes of poverty.

Source: Harvard University Archives. Harvard University, Examination Papers, 1873-1915. Box 8, Bound vol. Examination Papers 1908-09 (HUC 7000.25), pp. 36-37.

Image Source: Harvard football poster (1907) by F. Earl Christy. Library of Congress Prints and Photographs Division Washington, D.C.

 

 

Categories
Exam Questions France Germany Harvard History of Economics Methodology

Harvard. Exam for 19th century French and German Economics, Gay, 1906-07

Edwin Francis Gay (1867-1946) had spent over a decade studying history and economics in Europe before coming to Harvard in 1903. I am somewhat surprised that he could find even three students to take his graduate course that appears to have required a better-than-average reading knowledge of both German and French.

In 1902-03 Gay taught “Outlines of the Development of Economic Thought in Germany in the Nineteenth Century”.

In 1904-05 he then taught “German and French economists of the 19th century” but Harvard’s collection of printed economics exams for 1904-05 did not include Gay’s exam for the course.

Fortunately, the year-end examination from the academic year 1906-07 was printed and we have transcribed it below. Added bonus material: an English translation of the paragraph taken from a book written by the German economist Karl Bücher that students were expected to translate.

________________________

Course Enrollment

Economics 22. Professor Gay. — German and French Economists of the Nineteenth Century.

Total 3: 3 Graduates.

Source: Harvard University. Report of the President of Harvard College, 1906-1907, p. 71.

________________________

ECONOMICS 22
Year-end Examination, 1906-07

  1. Explain von Thünen’s wage theory. What is his contribution to economic method? How does it compare with Le Play’s?
  2. Compare the conceptions of distributive justice entertained by the French socialists with those of the Austrian school.
  3. Trace the development of the concept of pure profits in the German and French economists.
  4. Discuss the attack of the German historical school on the classical economists and its justification.
  5. Translate die following:
    “Zwei Dinge müssen auf diesem Gebiete den an den Kategorien der modernen Volkswirtschaft geschulten Kopf besonders befremden; die Häufigkeit, mit der unkörperliche Sachen („Verhältnisse“) zu wirtschaftlichen Gütern werden und dem Verkehre unterliegen, und ihre verkehrsrechtliche Behandlung als Immobilien. An ihnen ist so recht zu sehen, wie die beginnende Tauschwirtschaft den Spielraum, den ihr die damalige Produktionsordnung versagte, dadurch zu erweitern suchte, dass sie in täppischem Zugreifen fast alles zum Verkehrsgut machte und so die Sphäre des Privatrechts ins Ungemessene ausdehnte. Was hat man im Mittelalter nicht verliehen, verschenkt, verkauft und verpfändet! Die herrschaftliche Gewalt über Länder und Städte, Grafschafts- und Vogteirechte, Cent- und Gaugerichte, kirchliche Würden und Patronate, Bannrechte, Fähren und Wegerechte, Münze und Zoll, Jagd- und Fischereigerechtsame, Beholzungsrechte, Zehnten, Fronden, Grundzinsen und Renten, überhaupt Reallasten jeder Art. Wirtschaftlich betrachtet, teilen alle diese Rechte und Verhältnisse mit dem Grund und Boden die Eigentümlichkeit, nicht von dem Orte ihrer Ausübung entfernt und nicht beliebig vermehrt werden zu können.”

[Note: quote comes from Professor Karl Bücher, University of Leipzig. Die  Entstehung der Volkswirtschaft, Vorträge und Versuche, 3rd ed. (Tübingen, 1901), p. 153.]

Source: Harvard University Archives. Harvard University, Examination Papers 1873-1915. Box 8, Bound volume: Examination Papers, 1906-07; Papers Set for Final Examinations in History, Government, Economics,…,Music in Harvard College (June, 1907), pp. 43-44.

English translation of Question 5’s quote

There are two things in connection with this that must appear especially strange to a student of modern political economy, namely, the frequency with which immaterial things (relationships) become economic commodities and subjects of exchange, and their treatment under commercial law as real property. These show clearly how primitive exchange sought to enlarge the sphere denied it under the existing conditions of production by awkwardly transforming, into negotiable property, almost everything it could lay hold upon, and thus extending infinitely the domain of private law. What an endless variety of things in mediaeval times were lent, bestowed, sold, and pawned! — the sovereign power over territories and towns; county and bailiff’s rights; jurisdiction over hundreds and cantons; church dignities and patronages; suburban monopoly rights; ferry and road privileges; prerogatives of mintage and toll, of hunting and fishing; wood-cutting rights, tithes, statute labour, ground-rents, and revenues; in fact charges of every kind falling upon the land. Economically considered, all these rights and “relationships”” share with land the peculiarity that they cannot be removed from the place where they are enjoyed, and that they cannot be multiplied at will.

Source: Karl Bücher, Industrial Evolution, third German edition (German title: Die Entstehung der Volkswirtschaft, Vorträge und Versuche. English translation by S. Morley Wickett, Lecturer on Political Economy and Statistics, University of Toronto. New York: Henry Hold and Company, 1907, p. 131.

Image Source: Johann Heinrich von Thünen (Wikimedia Commons). Frédéric Le Play (Social History Portal)

Categories
Exam Questions Harvard Methodology

Harvard. Course enrollment, description, final exam. Economic Research Methods. Carver, 1904-1905

 

With this post we add Professor Thomas Nixon Carver’s exam questions for a graduate course on methods of economic investigation to our larger data base of economics examination questions. This was the fourth time that Carver offered this particular course at Harvard. The scope of his teaching portfolio was by far the broadest of the department, ranging across economic theory, sociology, schemes of economic reform, and agricultural economics so it is hardly surprising that he would have judged himself competent to teach/preach methodology too. 

The last question reveals his trinity of economic methods: historical, statistical and analytical. Judging merely from Carver’s exam questions here, I would hazard a guess that this course might have been considered a “snap” course. I have no explanation for the relatively low enrollment figures, that is unless he assigned significant amounts of German language texts. Taussig did that earlier.

__________________________

“Methods of Investigation”
in other years

Economics 13 (Scope and Methods) in 1895-96, Taussig.

Economics 13 (Scope and Methods) in 1896-97, Not Offered.

Economics 13 (Scope and Methods) in 1897-98, Ashley.

Economics 13 (Methods) in 1898-99, Taussig.

Economics 13 (Methods) in 1899-1900, Not Offered.

Economics 13 (Methods) in 1900-01, Carver.

Economics 13 (Methods) in 1902-03, Carver.

Economics 13 (Methods) in 1903-04, Carver.

Economics 12 (Scope and Methods) from 1914-15, Carver.

__________________________

Course Enrollment
1904-05

‡Economics 13 1hf. Professor Carver. — Methods of Economic Investigation.

Total 4: 2 Graduates, 2 Seniors.

Source: Harvard University. Report of the President of Harvard College, 1904-1905, p. 75.

__________________________

Course Description
1904-05

[Economics] ‡*13 1hf. Methods of Economic Investigation. Half-course (first half-year). Tu., Th., at 2.30. Professor Carver.

Course 13 will examine the methods by which the leading writers of modern times have approached economic questions, and the range which they have given their inquiries; and will consider the advantage of different methods, and the expediency of a wider or narrower scope of investigation. These inquiries will necessarily include a consideration of the logic of the social sciences. Methods of reasoning, methods of investigation, and methods of exposition will be considered separately, and the sources and character of the facts which are essential to economic science will be examined. Cairnes’ Logical Method of Political Economy and Keynes’ Scope and Method of Political Economy will be carefully examined. At the same time selected passages from the writings of Mill, Jevons, Marshall, and the Austrian writers will be studied, with a view to analyzing the nature and scope of the reasoning.

Course 13 is designed mainly for students who take or have taken Course 2 or Course 15; but it is open to mature students having a general acquaintance with economic theory.

Source: Harvard University. Faculty of Arts and Sciences. Division of History and Political Science Comprising the Departments of History and Government and Economics, 1904-05 (May 16, 1904), p. 49.

__________________________

ECONOMICS 131
Year-end Examination, 1904-05

  1. Discuss the question of the subdivisions of economics.
  2. Is it possible to discuss economic questions without passing ethical judgements? Explain and give examples.
  3. Of what use are mathematical formulae and diagrams in economics?
  4. Compare the historical and the analytical methods in their applicability to the following questions: (1) Is the world likely to become over populated? (2) Would communism tend to increase the rate of multiplication?
  5. Is there any relation between the theory of probabilities and any class of economic laws? Explain.
  6. By what logical method is it possible to distinguish the product of a given factor from that of a number of coöperating factors of production?
  7. Do economists make use of pure hypotheses such as are used in the physical sciences? Give reasons for your answer.
  8. What do you conceive to be the true relation of the historical method, the statistical method and the analytical method to one another.

Source: Harvard University Archives. Harvard University, Examination Papers 1873-1915. Box 7, Bound volume: Examination Papers, 1904-05;  Papers Set for Final Examinations in History, Government, Economics,…,Music in Harvard College (June, 1905), p. 33.

Image Source: Thomas Nixon Carver photograph from the November 11, 1916 issue of the Harvard Illustrated Magazine, p. 110.Colorized by Economics in the Rear-view Mirror.

Categories
Economist Market Exam Questions Harvard Methodology

Harvard. Final exam questions for economic methods course. Carver, 1903-04

This semester-long course on methods of economic investigation taught by Thomas Nixon Carver was listed as one being “primarily for graduates”. Only the introductory course of the department was considered “primarily for undergraduates” while the bulk of course offerings were deemed appropriate for both graduate and undergraduate students. Judging from the questions, this course appears to have been little more than a leisurely trot through John Neville Keynes, The Scope and Method of Economics (1897, 2nd ed.) along with Cairnes’ Logical Method of Political Economy (1875, 2nd ed.).

___________________________

Related previous posts

___________________________

Course Enrollment

Economics 13 1hf. Professor Carver. Methods of Economic Investigation.

Total 11: 5 Graduates, 3 Seniors, 3 Radcliffe

Source: Harvard University. Report of the President of Harvard College, 1903-1904, p. 67.

___________________________

ECONOMICS 13
Mid-Year Examination. 1903-04

Discuss the following topics.

  1. The relation of economics and ethics.
  2. The departments of political economy.
  3. The fields for the observation of economic phenomena.
  4. The nature of an economic law.
  5. The use of hypotheses in economics.
  6. The relation of theoretical analysis to historical investigation.
  7. The place of diagrams and mathematical formulae in economics.
  8. The methods of investigating the causes of poverty.
  9. The methods of determining the effects of immigration on the population of the United States.
  10. The place of direct observation in economic study.

Source:  Harvard University Archives. Harvard University, Mid-year examinations 1852-1943. Box 7, Bound volume: Examination Papers, Mid-Years, 1903-04.

Image SourceHarvard Classbook 1906. Colorized by Economics in the Rear-View Mirror.

Categories
George Mason Methodology Suggested Reading Syllabus

George Mason. Course readings for Economic Philosophy. Buchanan and Vanberg, 1990

 

This post is an experiment in transcription. The HOPE Center at Duke University has started recently to provide pdf scans of syllabi from Ed Tower’s Eno River Press collection and I wondered how easy it would be to use the text-recognition software in Adobe Acrobat Pro to extract digital versions of the syllabi. It turns out that at least for this initial attempt, tweaking and correction of the OCR text required considerably less blood, sweat and tears than a standard typed transcription would have. 

Like other members of the greater community of historians of economics, I eagerly await further scans from the Tower volumes by the HOPE Center. From time to time, I’ll convert a scanned syllabus to add to the collection of digital material posted at Economics in the Rear-view Mirror. Links to the original scans will be provided whenever available. 

_________________________

George Mason University
SPRING 1990

Economics 827: ECONOMIC PHILOSOPHY
James M. Buchanan, Viktor J. Vanberg

Purpose and theme:

The purpose of this course is to discuss some of the issues at the foundations of economics as a social science. It will cover topics like the following (the numbers behind the titles refer to the reading list):

— Economics as moral philosophy (1, 13, 15, 20).

— Welfare economics and political economy (2, 3, 4).

— Methodological and normative individualism (14, 22).

— Subjectivism and opportunity costs (9, 12, 30).

— Utilitarianism and contractarianism (5, 16, 18, 19, 24).

— Agreement in exchange, in politics and in science (10, 29).

— Liberty, voluntariness and efficiency (7, 26).

— Justice as fairness and distributive justice (6, 11, 21, 23, 24).

— Homo economicus, rational choice and rule-following (8, 25, 27).

— Economics and morality (17, 19, 28).

Organization:

The constituting meeting for this course will be held on January 23, 7:20 p.m., in room R 2600. The core part of this course will be taught during the two-weeks period February 19 through March 2 in the library of the center for Study of Public Choice, George’s Hall, from 8:30 a.m. to 11:00 a.m. (daily Mon. through Fri.).

Grading:

Grades will be determined on daily (one page) protocols during the ‘core-period’ and a longer (15-20 pages) paper on a subject to be chosen between student and instructor.

Reading List:

(A set of xerox-copies of the following titles will be available from Kinko’s Copies, University Mall).

  1. Albert, Hans “Knowledge and Decision” chpt. 3 in H. Albert Treatise in Critical Reason Princeton University Press 1985, 71-101.
  2. Buchanan, James M. “Social Choice, Democracy, and Free Markets” in Fiscal Theory and Political Economy Chapel Hill 1960, 75-89.
  3. — , — “Positive Economics, Welfare Economics, and Political Economy” in Fiscal Theory and Political Economy Chapel Hill 1960, 105-124.
  4. — , — “The Relevance of Pareto Optimality” in The Journal of Conflict Resolution 6, 1962, 341-354.
  5. — , — “Marginal Notes on Reading Political Philosophy” in J. M. Buchanan and G. Tullock The Calculus of Consent Ann Arbor 1965, 307-322.
  6. — , -— “Notes on Justice in Contract” in Freedom in Constitutional Contract Texas A&M University Press 1977, 123-134.
  7. — , — “Criteria for a Free Society: Definition, Diagnosis, and Prescription” in Freedom in Constitutional Contract Texas A&M University Press 1977, 287-299.
  8. — , — “ls Economics the Science of Choice?” in What Should Economists Do? Liberty Press 1979, 39-63.
  9. — , — “General Implications of Subjectivism in Economics” in What Should Economists Do?” Liberty Press 1979, 81-91.
  10. — , — “The Potential for Tyranny in Politics as Science” in Liberty, Market and State New York University Press 1985, 40-54.
  11. — , — “Rules for a Fair Game: Contractarian Notes on Distributive Justice” in Liberty, Market and State New York University Press 1985, 123-139.
  12. — , — “L.S.E. Cost Theory in Retrospect” in Economics Between Predictive Science and Moral Philosophy Texas A&M University Press 1987, 141-151.
  13. — , — “Political Economy and Social Philosophy” in P. Koslowski, ed., Economics and Philosophy, Tuebingen 1985.
  14. — , — “The Foundations for Normative Individualism” mimeographed, Center for Study of Public Choice.
  15. Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock “The Politics of the Good Society,” Chpt. 20 in The Calculus of Consent Ann Arbor 1965, 297-306.
  16. Gauthier, David “On the Refutation of Utilitarianism” in H B. Miller and W. H. Williams (eds.) The Limits of Utilitarianism University of Minnesota Press 1982, 144-163.
  17. — , — “Maximization Constrained: The Rationality of Cooperation” in R. Campbell and L. Sowden (eds.) Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation Vancouver 1985, 75-93.
  18. Hahn, Frank “On Some Difficulties of the Utilitarian Economist” in A. Sen and B. Williams (eds.) Utilitarianism and Beyond Cambridge University Press 1982, 187-198.
  19. Harsanyi John C. ”Morality and Social Welfare” chpt. 4 in J. C. Harsanyi Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations Cambridge University Press 1977, 48-64.
  20. Hayek, Friedrich A. “Kinds of Rationalism” in F. A. Hayek Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics The University of Chicago Press 1967, 82-95.
  21. — , — “The Atavism of Social Justice” in F. A. Hayek New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas The University of Chicago Press 1978, 57-68.
  22. Lachmann, Ludwig M. “Methodological Individualism and the Market Economy” in L. M. Lachmann Capital, Expectations, and the Market Process Kansas City 1977, 149-165.
  23. Nozick, Robert “Distributive Justice” chpt. 7 in R. Nozick Anarchy, State, and Utopia New York 1974, 149-164 + 183-189.
  24. Rawls, John “Justice as Fairness” chpt. 1 in J. Rawls A Theory of Justice Harvard University Press 1971, 3-27.
  25. Sen, Amartya “Behaviour and the Concept of Preference” in J. Elster (ed.) Rational Choice Basil Blackwell 1986, 60-81.
  26. Vanberg, Viktor “Individual Choice and Institutional Constraints – TheNormative Element in Classical and Contractarian Liberalism” in Analyse & Kritik Vol. 8, 1986, 113-149.
  27. — , — “Rational Choice, Rule-Following and Institutions” mimeographed, Center for Study of Public Choice, 1989, 49pp.
  28. Vanberg, Viktor and James M. Buchanan “Rational Choice and Moral Order” in Analyse & Kritik 10, 1988, 138-160.
  29. Vanberg, Viktor and James M. Buchanan “Interests and Theories in Constitutional Choice” in Journal of Theoretical Politics 1, 1989, 49-62.
  30. Wiseman, Jack “General Equilibrium or Market Process: An Evaluation” in J. Wiseman Cost, Choice and Political Economy Edward Elgar 1989, 213-233.

Readings suggested for further study:

Buchanan, James M. Cost and Choice — An Inquiry in Economic Theory Chicago 1969.

— , — Freedom in Constitutional Contract Texas A&M University Press 1977.

— , — Economics — Between Predictive Science and Moral Philosophy Texas A&M University Press 1987.

Gauthier, David Morals By Agreement Oxford: Clarendon Press 1986.

Gray, John Liberalism Open University Press 1986.

Hayek, Friedrich A. Law, Legislation and Liberty University of Chicago Press 1974, 1976, 1979 (three volumes).

— , — The Fatal Conceit — The Errors of Socialism London: Routledge 1988 (Vol. 1 of The Collected Works of Friedrich August Hayek).

Nozick, Robert Anarchy, State, and Utopia New York: Basic Books 1974.

Rawls, John A Theory of Justice Harvard University Press 1971.

Vanberg, Viktor Morality and Economics — De Moribus Est Disputandum, New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1988 (Social Philosophy and Policy Center, Original Papers No. 7).

Source: Transcribed from the images scanned from the Eno River Press volumes of syllabuses of economics coursescompiled and published by Ed Tower that he donated to the History of Political Economy (HOPE) Center at Duke University.

Image Sources: Buchanan portrait from the Nobel prize website. Vanberg portrait from the Walter Eucken Institut website.

Categories
Methodology

University College London. Lecture on the future of political economy. Jevons, 1876

 

William Stanley Jevons used the opportunity of his inaugural lecture as Professor of Political Economy at University College London to muse on the future of political economy using the discussion at the Centennial Celebration by the London Political Economy Club of the publication of The Wealth of Nations for his point of departure. He positions himself in the Methodenstreit as an eclectic advocate of formal theoretical methods who gladly includes historical and statistical methods in the economist’s toolbox. The fault of the partisans of induction that Jevons sees are their claims that historical observation is not just necessary in the search for valid economic laws but that it alone is sufficient. In many ways like Carl Menger, Jevons only argues for the necessity of abstraction and deduction: “In these and many other cases, people argue, more or less consciously, that because a certain thing is true or useful, therefore other things are not true or not useful. “

_________________________

THE FUTURE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY
W. Stanley Jevons

Introductory Lecture at the opening of the Session 1876-7, at University College, London, Faculty of Arts and Laws.

The year 1876 is remarkable as being the hundredth anniversary of at least two important events. On the other side of the Atlantic, the Americans are celebrating the birth of a great nation. On this side of the water we ought to be celebrating the publication of a great book — a book to which we owe, in as great a degree as to any other circumstance, the wealth and prosperity of this kingdom. It is curious to observe, indeed, that these two centenaries are in a certain respect antithetic to each other. While we attribute our wealth to the establishment of the free trade principles which Smith advocated, the American Government yet maintains a fiscal system direct and avowed antagonism to those principles.

The enormous wealth of the United States has been created by the freedom and energy of internal trade acting upon natural resources of unexampled richness. It cannot for a moment be doubted that their wealth would be far greater still were external commerce in the States as free as internal commerce. To us, dwelling and working in this comparatively speaking very small island, endowed with no remarkable natural resources, except coal and iron, —to us, the freedom of external commerce is everything. This freedom we may properly attribute to the writings of Adam Smith, even more than to the labours of Gladstone, or Cobden, or Bright, or any of the great statesmen who actually carried the doctrines of Smith into effect.

We ought, therefore, to be celebrating the publication of the “Wealth of Nations,” and the memory of its author; but are we doing so? With a single exception, I am unacquainted with any public ceremony, or anything tending to mark this as a centennial year in Great Britain. Perhaps this is because we are not a people accustomed to commemorations of the sort. If I recollect rightly, even the Shakespearean jubilee was rather a failure. However this may be, there has been one exception, and that was a most suitable commemoration of Adam Smith. On the 31st of May last, the Political Economy Club held a grand dinner and a special discussion in honour of the hundredth anniversary of the publication of the “Wealth of Nations.”

Probably, when people saw this dinner described in the newspapers, their first thought was, “What is the Political Economy Club? We never heard of it before.” I may, therefore, explain briefly, that the Political Economy Club has pursued an inconspicuous, but very useful career for more than half a century. Whether its continued existence be due to the excellence of its monthly dinners, — in respect of which the club does not seem to study economy — or to the interest of the economical debates which follow each dinner, I will not attempt to decide. Certain it is, however, that the club was founded in the year 1821 by Ricardo, Malthus, Tooke, James Mill, Grote, Cazenove, and other distinguished men, and that since its foundation it has included as members nearly all English political economists. John Stuart Mill especially was, for many years, a leading member, and first propounded at its table the doctrines advocated in his economical works.

It was no doubt most suitable that such a body should celebrate the establishment in England of the science they cultivate, and the centenary dinner held last May was in some respects a very remarkable one. Mr. Gladstone was in the chair, with Mr. Lowe on the one hand, and M. Léon Say, the present French Minister of Finance, on the other hand. The company included a body of statesmen, economists, and statists, British, Continental, and American, such as are seldom seen together. It is true that the statesmen had it mostly their own way, and in the presence of Gladstone and Lowe, and a real French Minister of Finance, the company appeared to care little what mere literary economists thought about Adam Smith. But I shall on the present occasion be so bold as incidentally to review and criticize some of the opinions which were put forth at the dinner, a full and carefully revised report of the speeches having been printed by Messrs. Longman, under the superintendence of the committee of the club.

Mr. Lowe opened the debate in a most interesting survey and eulogium of Adam Smith and his works. He concluded with some remarks upon the results which have followed from Smith’s writings, and upon what yet remains to be achieved by political economy. I was much struck with the desponding tone in which Mr. Lowe spoke of the future of the science I have the honour to teach in this college. He seems to think that the work of the science is to a great extent finished. He said: —

“I do not myself feel very sanguine that there is a very large field— at least, according to the present state of mental and commercial knowledge— for political economy, beyond what I have mentioned; but I think that very much depends upon the degree in which other sciences are developed. Should other sciences relating to mankind, which it is the barbarous jargon of the day to call Sociology, take a spring and get forward in any degree towards the certainty attained by political economy, I do not doubt that their development would help in the development of this science; but at present, so far as my own humble opinion goes, I am not sanguine as to any very large or any very startling development of political economy. I observe that the triumphs which have been gained, have been rather in demolishing that which has been found to be undoubtedly bad and erroneous, than in establishing new truth; and imagine that, before we can attain new results, we must be furnished from without with new truths to which our principles may be applied. The controversies which we now have in political economy, although they offer a capital exercise for the logical faculties, are not of the same thrilling importance as those of earlier days; the great work has been done.”

I am far from denying that there is much to support, or at any rate to suggest, this view of the matter. Some of the greatest reforms which economists can point out the need of have been accomplished, and there is certainly no single work to be done comparable to the establishment of free trade. But this does not prevent the existence of an indefinitely great sphere of useful work which economists could accomplish, if their science were adequate to its duties. To a certain extent, again, I agree with Mr. Lowe that there is much in the present position of our science to cause despondency. A very general impression to this effect seems to exist. Some of the newspapers hinted in reference to the centenary dinner that the political economists had better be celebrating the obsequies of their science than its jubilee. The Pall-Mall Gazette especially thought that Mr. Lowe’s task was to explain the decline, not the consummation, of economical science. Perhaps with many people the wish was father of the thought. I am aware that political economists have always been regarded as cold-blooded beings, devoid of the ordinary feelings of humanity — little better, in fact, than vivisectionists. I believe that the general public would be happier in their minds for a little time if political economy could be shown up as imposture, like the greater part of what is called spiritualism.

It must be allowed, too, that there have been for some years back premonitory symptoms of disruption of the old orthodox school of economists. Respect for the names of Ricardo and Mill seems no longer able to preserve unanimity. J. S. Mill himself, in the later years of his life, gave up one of the doctrines on which he had placed much importance in his works. One economist after another — Thornton, Cairnes, Leslie, Macleod, Longe, Hearn, Musgrave — have protested against some one or other of the articles of the old Ricardian creed.

At the same time foreign economists, such as De Laveleye, Courcelle-Seneuil, Cournot, Walras, and others, have taken a course almost entirely independent of the predominant English school. So far has this discontent gone, that Mr. Bagehot has been induced to re-examine the fundamental postulates of economy from their very foundation, in his most acute papers published in the Fortnightly Review. He remarks (p. 216, Feb. 1, 1876): —

“Notwithstanding these triumphs, the position of our political economy is not altogether satisfactory. It lies rather dead in the public mind. Not only it does not excite the same interest as formerly, but there is not exactly the same confidence in it. Younger men either do not study it, or do not feel that it comes home to them, and that it matches with their most living ideas … They ask, often hardly knowing it, will this ‘Science,’ as it claims to be, harmonize with what we now know to be sciences, or bear to be tried as we now try sciences? And they are not sure of the answer.”

In short, it comes to this — that one hundred years after the first publication of the “Wealth of Nations” we find the state of the science to be almost chaotic. There is certainly less agreement now about what political economy is than there was thirty or fifty years ago. Under these circumstances, I will now draw your attention for a short time to the apparently rival sects which seem likely to arise from the break up of the old Ricardian school.

In the first place, it is impossible to ignore the fact that there has been gradually rising into prominence a school of writers who take a very radical view of the reforms required in our science. They call in question the validity even of the deductive method on which Smith mainly relied. They hold that the science must be entirely recast in method and materials, and that it must take the form of an historical or archaeological science. At the centenary dinner this view of the matter was boldly stated by one of the most distinguished of European economists — namely, M. de Laveleye. His own words, translated into English, will best explain his opinions: —

“It is principally at this point that there has recently arisen a division in the ranks of economists. Some, the old school, whom, for want of a better name, I will call the Orthodox School, believe that everything regulates itself by the effect of natural laws. The other school, which its adversaries have named the Socialists of the Chair, the ‘Katheder-socialisten,’ but which we ought rather to call the Historical School, or as the Germans say, the ‘Realist School;’ this school holds that distribution is governed in part doubtless by free contract; but also, and still more, by civil and political institutions, by religious beliefs, by moral sentiments, by custom and historical tradition. You see that there opens itself here an immense field of studies, comprehending the relations of political economy with morals, justice, right, religion, history, and connecting it to the ensemble of social science. That in my humble opinion is the actual mission of political economy. This is the path pursued by nearly all German economists, several of whom have a European reputation, such as Rau, Roscher, Knies, Nasse, Schäffle, Schmoller; in Italy by a group of writers alaready well known, Minghetti, Luzzati, Forti; in France, by Wolowski, Lavergne, Passy, Courcelle-Seneuil, Leroy-Beaulieu; and in England by authors, whom it is unnecessary to name or estimate here, because you know them better than I.”

There is certainly no difficulty in mentioning a series of distinguished English economists who have shown a propensity to the historical treatment of the science. To begin with, A. Smith would no doubt be claimed by the historical school, for there is a strong historical element running through his book. Not only does “The Wealth of Nations” contain special historical inquiries like that concerning the value of silver, the chapter on agricultural systems, or the whole book upon “The Different Progress of Opulence in Different Nations,” but the whole work teems with concrete illustrations or verifications drawn from the history of many countries. As has been well remarked, Adam Smith had some of the many-sidedness at which all have wondered in Shakespeare, and it is singular testimony to the completeness of his method, that while Mr. Lowe claimed him, and I think correctly, as a deductive economist, another speaker. Professor Rogers, held him to be the practical Bacon of economical science. The fact, I believe, is that Smith combined deductive reasoning with empirical verification in the manner required by the complete inductive method.

But to proceed, we find that the essay of Malthus on Population far from being, as many people probably suppose, a collection of rash generalisations and hypotheses, consists mainly of a most careful inquiry into historical and statistical facts concerning the numbers and conditions of mankind in all parts of the world. It is a model of inductive inquiry so far as information was available in his day. The essay of Richard Jones on the “Distribution of Wealth and the Forms of Land Tenure in Different Countries,’’ is a far less celebrated book, but displays the same careful spirit of inquiry into the past or present condition of men. Mr. Samuel Laing, again, in his well-known and most interesting works, takes the same position, and has studied upon the spot the economy of Norway, Sweden, France, Prussia, and Switzerland, somewhat in the manner that Arthur Young studied France and Great Britain in the last century. The general conclusion of Mr. Laing is that every country has a political economy of its own, suitable to its own physical circumstances and its own national character.

Passing over the minor works of Banfield, Burton, and others, it is impossible to overlook the recent admirable research of Professor Thorold Rogers, “On the History of Agriculture and Prices in England, from 1259 to 1400” (published by the Clarendon Press). [Volume I; Volume II] In this book Professor Rogers has certainly pursued the historical and inductive method with unbounded industry and remarkable success. He has made us better acquainted with the economy of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries than we are with that of the eighteenth. In the fascinating works of Sir Henry Maine, too, especially his last work on “The Early History of Institutions,” there is much historical inquiry bearing upon economical science.

Perhaps the most recent of all declarations in favour of the inductive study of the laws of wealth, is that of Sir George Campbell, who in his inaugural address as President of the Economical and Statistical Section of the British Association, at the late Glasgow meeting, spoke as follows:—

“There was a time when it seems to have been supposed that political economy was a science regulated by natural laws, so fixed that safe results could be attained by deductive reasoning. But since it has become apparent that men do not in fact invariably follow the laws of money-making, pure and simple, that economic action is affected by moral causes which cannot be exactly measured it becomes more and more evident, that we cannot safely trust to a chain of deduction; we must test every step by an accurate observation of facts, and induction from them.”

Upon this and other statements I shall have to make some remarks presently.

It is, however, Professor Cliffe Leslie who has placed himself at the front of the inductive and historical school of economists in this country, by the thoroughness as well as the ability of the essay in which he declares his revolt from the old orthodox school. In a remarkable paper, printed in the Dublin University essays published under the title of “Hermathena,” he calls in question altogether the validity of the deductive reasoning which Mr. Lowe considered the most valuable feature in the “Wealth of Nations.” He considers the generally-recognised laws of economy to be rude generalisations, obtained by a superficial and unphilosophical process of abstraction. No attempt, he thinks, has been made to measure the relative force of economical principles in different states of society, or to allow for multitudes of disturbing causes.

“Had the actual operation of the motives in question,” he says, “been investigated, it would have been seen to vary widely in different states of society, and under different conditions. The love of distinction, or of social position, for example, may either counteract the desire of wealth, or greatly add to its force as a motive to industry and accumulation. It may lead one man to make a fortune, another to spend it. At the head of the inquiry into the causes on which the amount of the wealth of nations depends is the problem — what are the conditions which direct the energies and determine the actual occupations and pursuits of mankind in different ages and countries?”….
‘‘Enough,” he continues, “has been said in proof that the abstract à priori and deductive method yields no explanation of the causes which regulate either the nature or the amount of wealth…. The truth is, that the whole economy of every nation, as regards the occupations and pursuits of both sexes, the nature, amount, distribution, and consumption of wealth, is the result of a long evolution, in which there has been both continuity and change, and of which the economical side is only a particular aspect or phase. And the laws of which it is the result must be sought in history, and the general laws of society and social evolution.”

These extracts indicate the line of thought by which Professor Leslie has been led to regard the general theorems of Ricardo as mere “guesses,” and the deductive theory of political economy as barren, if not false. Now I am far from thinking that the historical treatment of our science is false or useless. On the contrary, I consider it to be indispensable. The present economical state of society cannot possibly be explained by theory alone. We must take into account the long past, out of which we are constantly emerging. Whether we call it sociology or not, we must have some scientific treatment of the principles of evolution as manifested in every branch of social existence. Accordingly, M. de Laveleye, Professor Cliffe Leslie, or M. Lavergne, may very properly do for political economy what Sir Henry Maine has done for jurisprudence — namely, show that every law, custom, or social fact is the product of the past, historical or forgotten.

But it is surprising how often men, even of the highest powers, fall into a logical fallacy which has not, I think, been dubbed with any special name, but might fitly be called the fallacy of exclusiveness. There are too many in the present day who advocate the teaching of physical science, and imply in the mode of their advocacy that moral, classical, or other studies are to be discountenanced. It is most common to find people speaking of inductive reasoning, as if it were entirely distinct and opposite to deductive reasoning, the fact being, however, as I believe, that deduction is a necessary element of induction.

In these and many other cases, people argue, more or less consciously, that because a certain thing is true or useful, therefore other things are not true or not useful. Some tendency of this sort might be suspected by the reader of the last two chapters of Sir Henry Maine’s “Early History of Institutions,” in which he discusses the relation of his own historical treatment of jurisprudence to the systems of Hobbes, Bentham, and especially Austin. Sir Henry Maine has conclusively shown that the investigation of the origin and development of law is essential to the understanding of the jurisprudence of any people; but it does not follow, and I do not understand Sir Henry Maine to assert, that an abstract and perfect scheme of jurisprudence, like that which Austin gave to the world in this college, is therefore devoid of truth and usefulness. Now the case of political economy is exactly parallel to this.

I cannot easily conceive any more interesting or useful subject of study than that which Professor Leslie advocates and engages in. It is absolutely essential that we should view the present by the light of the past; but I differ from him entirely when he holds that historical political economy is to destroy and replace the abstract theory which has previously held the place of the science. Does it follow that because palaeontology is now established as an all-important science of an historical character, therefore animal physiology, or the chemistry of animal substances, is false? Any group of objects may be studied, either as regards the laws of action of their component parts, irrespective of time, or as regards the successive forms produced from time to time under the action of those laws. Now the laws of political economy treat of the relations between human wants and the available natural objects and human labour by which they may be satisfied. These laws are so simple in their foundation that they would apply, more or less completely, to all human beings of whom we have any knowledge. The laws of property are very different in different countries and states of society. They seem to be in a very rudimentary state among the Eskimo. According to Dr. Rinks, if one Eskimo man has two boats and another has none, the latter has a right to borrow one of the two boats; and it is further said that it is not the custom among the Eskimo to return borrowed articles. Now this is of course a very different state of things from what obtains among us. Nevertheless we can trace in this transaction of the borrowed boat the simple principles which are at the basis of economy. The most fundamental of its laws is that of Senior and Banfield —namely, that human wants are limited in extent. One boat is very useful, if not essential, to an Eskimo; a second boat is much less useful to a man who has already one boat, but it is highly useful if passed into the hands of a boatless neighbour. The elements of value are present here as in the most complicated operations of our corn or stock exchanges. I should not despair of tracing the action of the postulates of political economy among some of the more intelligent classes of animals. Dogs certainly have strong though perhaps limited ideas of property, as you will soon discover if you interfere between a dog and his bone.

I come to the conclusion, then, that the first principles of political economy are so widely true and applicable, that they may be considered universally true as regards human nature. Historical political economy, so far from displacing the theory of economy, will only exhibit and verify the long-continued action of its laws in most widely different states of society. M. de Laveleye and Professor Leslie may succeed in constituting a new science, but they will not utterly revolutionise and destroy the old one in the way they seem to suppose.

The fact is it will no longer be possible to treat political economy as if it were a single undivided and indivisible science. The advantages of the division of labour are as great and indispensable in the pursuit of knowledge as in manual industry; and it is out of the question that political economy alone should fail to avail itself of these advantages. Differentiation, as Mr. Spencer would say, must go on. I should be afraid of tiring you if I were to attempt to trace out in detail the several divisions into which political economy will naturally fall apart. Not only will there be a number of branches, but there are actually two or three different ways in which the division will take place.

There is, firstly, the old distinction of the laws of the science, according as they treat of the production, exchange, distribution, or consumption of wealth. In this respect economy may be regarded as an aggregate of two or more different sciences, there being, in fact, little connection between the principles which should guide us in production, and those which apply in distribution or consumption.

To readers of J. S. Mill’s “Principles of Political Economy,” indeed, it may sound strange to hear of consumption as one of the chief branches of the science. Though named last, as being last in the order of time, consumption is evidently the most important of the processes through which commodities pass, because things are only produced in order that they may be consumed usefully. It is unaccountable, then, and quite paradoxical, that English economists should, with few exceptions, ignore the most important branch of their own science, especially after it has been duly treated by J. B. Say, Storch, Courcelle-Seneuil, and many other continental writers, as well as by the excellent Australian economist, Professor Hearn.

Passing now to a second aspect, political economy will naturally be divided according as it is abstract or concrete. The theory of the science consists of those general laws which are so simple in nature, and so deeply grounded in the constitution of man and the outer world, that they remain the same throughout all those ages which are within our consideration. But though the laws are the same they may receive widely different applications in the concrete. The primary laws of motion are the same, whether they be applied to solids, liquids, or gases, though the phenomena obeying those laws are apparently so different. Just as there is a general science of mechanics, so we must have a general science or theory of economy. Here, again, there is a division of opinion. There are those who think that, dealing as the science does with quantities, economy must necessarily be a mathematical science, if it is anything at all. There are those, on the other hand, who, like the late Professor Cairnes, contest, and some who even ridicule, the notion of representing truths relating to human affairs in mathematical symbols. It may be safely asserted, however, that if English economists persist in rejecting the mathematical view of their science, they will fall behind their European contemporaries. How many English students, or even professors, I should like to know, have sought out the papers of the late Dr. Whewell, printed in the Cambridge Philosophical Transactions, [Mathematical Exposition of some Doctrines of Political Economy. Read March 2 and 14, 1829;  Mathematical Exposition of some of the Leading Doctrines in Mr. Ricardo’s “Principles of Political Economy and Taxation.” Read April 18 and May 2, 1831] in which he gives his view of the mode of applying mathematics to our science? What English publisher, I may ask again, would for a moment entertain the idea of reprinting a series of mathematical works on political economy? Yet this is what is being done in Italy by Professor Gerolamo Boccardo, the very learned and distinguished editor of the “Nuova Enciclopedia Italiana.” Professor Boccardo has also prefixed to the series a remarkable treatise of his own on the application of the quantitative method to economic and social science in general. This series, which forms the third portion of the well-known “Bibliotheca Economista,” will be completed with an Italian translation of the works of Professor Léon Walras, now Rector of the Academy of Lausanne, who has in recent years independently established the fact that the laws of supply and demand, and all the phenomena of value, may be investigated algebraically and illustrated geometrically. From inquiries of this sort the curious conclusion emerges, that equilibrium of exchange of goods resembles in mathematical conditions the equilibrium of weights upon a lever of the first order. In the latter case one weight multiplied by its arm must exactly equal the other weight multiplied by its arm. So, in an act of exchange, the commodity given multiplied by its degree of utility must equal the quantity of commodity received multiplied by its degree of utility. The theory of economy proves to be, in fact, the mechanics of utility and self-interest.

Now, too, that attention is at last being given to the mathematical character of the science, it is becoming apparent that a series of writers in France, Germany, Italy, and England have made attempts towards a mathematical theory. Their works have been almost unnoticed, or, at any rate, forgotten, mainly on account of the prejudice against the line of inquiry they adopted. It is much to be desired that some competent mathematician and economist should seek these works out and prepare a compendious abstract of their contents, in the manner of Mr. Todhunter’s valuable histories of mathematical science. On the present occasion I cannot do more than mention the names of some of the principal writers referred to, such as Lang, Kroeneke, Buquoy, Dupuit, Von Thünen, Cazaux, Cournot, and Francesco Fuoco, on the Continent, and Whewell, Tozer, Lardner, Perronet Thompson, Fleming Jenkin, Alfred Marshall, and probably others, in Great Britain.

So much for the theory of economy which will naturally be one science, remaining the same throughout its applications, though it may be broken up into several parts, the theories of utility, of exchange, of labour, of interest, &c., partly corresponding to the old division of the science into the laws of consumption, exchange, distribution, production, and so forth. Concrete political economy, however, can hardly be called one science, but already consists of many extensive branches of inquiry. Currency, banking, the relations of labour and capital, those of landlord and tenant, pauperism, taxation, and finance, are some of the principal portions of applied political economy, all involving the same ultimate laws, manifested in most different circumstances. In a subject of such appalling extent and complexity as currency, for instance, we depend upon the laws of supply and demand, of consumption and production of commodities as applied to the precious metals or other materials of money. In the science of banking and the money market, we have a very difficult application of the same laws to capital in general. This separation of the concrete branches of the science is, however, sufficiently obvious and recognised, and I need not dwell further upon it. The general conclusion, then, to which I come is, that political economy must for the future be looked upon as an aggregate of sciences. A hundred years ago, it was very wise of A. Smith to attempt no sub-division, but to expound his mathematical theory (for I hold that his reasoning was really mathematical in nature) in conjunction with concrete applications and historical illustrations. He produced a work so varied in interest, so beautiful in style, and so full of instruction, that it attracted many readers, and convinced those that it attracted. But economists are no more bound to go on imitating Adam Smith in the accidental features of his work, than metaphysicians are bound to write in the form of platonic dialogues, or poets in the style of the Shakespearean drama. With the progress of industry, how many hundreds or even thousands of trades have sprung up since Smith wrote! With the progress of knowledge, how many sciences have been created, and sub-divided, again and again! The science of electricity has been almost entirely discovered since 1776, yet now it has its abstract mathematical theories, its concrete applications, and its many branches, treating of frictional or static electricity, dynamic electricity or galvanism, electro-chemistry, electro-magnetism, magnetism, terrestrial magnetism, atmospheric electricity, and so forth. Within the same century chemistry, if not born, has grown, and is now so vast a body of facts and laws that professors are appointed to teach different parts of it. Yet the political economist is expected to teach all parts of his equally extensive and growing science, and is lucky if he escape having to profess also the mental, metaphysical, and moral sciences generally.

Nor can I doubt that in the future new developments of the science of economy must take place. Whether it be a science or not, or one science or many sciences, there is certainly an immense work to be done by this or some closely related branches of knowledge. If necessity is the mother of invention, as people are so fond of saying, then many new sciences ought soon to be invented. When listening to the speeches at the centenary dinner, I was much struck with the contracted view which seemed to be entertained of the work remaining to be accomplished by economists. Mr. Gladstone spoke as follows: —

‘‘I am bound to say that this society has still got its work before it. … I do not mean to say that there is a great deal remaining to be done here in the way of direct legislation, yet there is something. It appears to me at least, that perhaps the question of the currency is one in which we are still, I think, in a backward condition; our legislation having been confined in the main to averting great evils rather than to establishing a system which, besides being sound, would be complete and logical. With that exception perhaps, not much remains in the province of direct legislation.”

Mr. Lowe also, as shown in a quotation from his speech already given took a similarly desponding view of the powers and province of economy. To my mind, however, our whole social system seems to bristle with questions which will have to be decided one way or the other, and to a great extent upon economical grounds. Whether I look at the homes of the mass of the people, at workhouses, or hospitals, whether I consider the gambling of the Stock Exchange, the perplexity of bankers, anxious at one time to get money, at another to get rid of it, the endless discussions of workmen and masters, the diversion of the lands of the country from their proper uses, the scandalous waste of endowments, I cannot help feeling that the work before economists is more than ample.

I cannot better illustrate the need of more accurate economic knowledge in some directions, than by adverting to one of the principal points in debate at the centenary dinner. Mr. Newmarch, the treasurer of the club, threw in an apple of discord when he expressed a hope that political economy would lead to a restriction of the sphere of government. He said:—

“On one of the points mentioned by Mr. Lowe, with respect to political economy in its relation to the future, I am sanguine enough to think that there be what may be called a large negative development of political economy, tending to produce an important and beneficial effect; and that is, such a development of political economy as will reduce the functions of government within a smaller and smaller compass. The full development of the principles of Adam Smith has been in no small danger for some time past; and one of the great dangers which now hangs over this country, is that the wholesome spontaneous operation of human interests and human desires, seems to be in course of rapid supersession by the erection of one government department after another, by the setting up of one set of inspectors after another, and by the whole time of parliament being taken up in attempting to do for the nation those very things which, if the teaching of the man whose name we are celebrating to-day, is to bear any fruit at all, the nation can do much better for itself.”

Now it would not create much surprise if, on a point like this, professional economists should differ, like doctors. Accordingly my predecessor, Mr. Courtney, the honorary secretary of the club, took occasion to protest against the doctrines of the honorary treasurer being considered as those accepted by the club, at least as regards legislation upon land tenure. But it was very interesting to find that the practical statesmen were quite as much divided as the economists upon this point. While some supported Mr. Newmarch, one whom I can never help admiring for his firm consistency, and the inestimable benefits which he has conferred upon this country in the passing of the Education Act, namely Mr. W. E. Forster, took the exactly opposite view.

“I am strongly of the contrary opinion,” he said, “that we cannot undertake the laissez-faire principle in the present condition of our politics or of parties in parliament, or in the general condition of the country. I gather from Mr. Newmarch’s remarks that he is an advocate of the old laissez-faire principle. Well, if we were all Mr. Newmarches, if we had nothing to deal with in the country but men like ourselves, we might do this. But we have to deal with weak people; we have to deal with people who have themselves to deal with strong people, who are borne down, who are tempted, who are unfortunate in their circumstances of life, and who will say to us, and say to us with great truth: What is your use as a parliament if you cannot help us in our weakness, and against those who are too strong for us?”

Now it is impossible to doubt that the laissez-faire principle properly applied is the wholesome and true one. It is that advocated by Adam Smith, and it is in obedience to this principle that our tariff has been reduced to the simplest possible form, that the navigation laws have been repealed, that masters and labourers have been left free to make their own bargains about wages, and that a hundred other ingenious pieces of legislation have been struck out of the Statute Book. But does it follow that because we repeal old pieces of legislation we shall need no new ones? On the contrary, as it seems to me, while population grows more numerous and dense, while industry becomes more complex and interdependent, as we travel faster and make use of more intense forces, we shall necessarily need more legislative supervision. It has been well said, I think by Professor Hodgson, that the labourer need only ask of the statesman what Diogenes asked of Alexander, that he should stand out of his light. How, it was quite proper and reasonable that Alexander should not obstruct the light of Diogenes; but what if other people should come and stand in Diogenes’ light, or, overlooking anachronisms, street musicians should disturb his sleep and render study impossible, or, finally, carrying companies should carelessly convey gunpowder close behind his tub and blow it to bits; would Alexander have been justified in standing calmly by and quoting laissez-faire doctrines like those of the French economists and Adam Smith? I think not, and I believe that it will be found impossible to dispense with more and more minute legislation.

The numerous elaborate bills which each government of England has in late years attempted to pass, but generally without success, is the best indication of the needs felt. But I quite agree with Mr. Newmarch and Mr. Lowe that we should not proceed in this path of legislative interference without most careful consideration from a theoretical, as well as a practical, point of view, of what we are doing. If such a thing is possible, we need a new branch of political and statistical science which shall carefully investigate the limits to the laissez-faire principle, and show where we want greater freedom and where less. It seems inconsistent that we should be preaching freedom of industry and commerce at the same time that we are hampering them with all kinds of minute regulations. But there may be no real inconsistency if we can show the existence of special reasons which override the general principle in particular cases. I am quite convinced, for instance, that the great mass of the people will not have healthy houses by the ordinary action of self-interest. The only chance of securing good sanitary arrangements is to pull down the houses which are hopelessly bad, as provided by an Act of the present ministry, and most carefully to superintend under legislative regulations all new houses that are built.

I will go a step farther, and assert that the utmost benefits may be, and, in fact, are secured to us by extensions of government action of a kind quite unsanctioned by the laissez-faire principle. I allude to the provision of public institutions of various sorts —libraries, museums, parks, free bridges.

Community of property is most wasteful in some cases, as in the old commons, or unpreserved oyster beds; but these are cases of the community of production. Community of consumption, on the contrary, is often most economical. The same book in a public library may serve a hundred or five hundred readers as well as one. The principle may be illustrated by the case of watches and clocks. On reasonable suppositions I have calculated that a private watch costs people on the average about one-fifteenth part of a penny for each look at the time of day; but a great public clock is none the worse, however many people may look at it. As a general rule, I should say that the average cost of public clocks is not more than one-one hundred and fiftieth of a penny for each look, securing an economy of ten times. The same principle may, however, be called into operation in a multitude of cases, most notably, however, as regards the weather. A well-appointed meteorological office with a system of weather forecasts will be a necessary part of every government, and will secure the utmost advantages to the community at a trifling cost. I see no reason, again, why our streets and roads should, as a general rule, be fit only for passing along and getting out of as quickly as you can. With a trifling expenditure they might often be converted into agreeable promenades, planted with trees, and furnished with seats at the public cost. Our idea of happiness in this country at present seems to consist in buying a piece of land if possible, and building a high wall round it. If a man can only secure, for instance, a beautiful view from his own garden and windows, he cares not how many thousands of other persons he cuts off from the daily enjoyment of that view. The rights of private property and private action are pushed so far that the general interests of the public are made of no account whatever.

But the nicest discrimination will be required to show what the government should do, and what it should leave to individuals to do. I do not in the least underestimate the wastefulness of government departments, but I believe that this wastefulness may be far more than counterbalanced in some cases by the economy of public property.

I have said enough I think to suggest that there are still great possibilities for us in the future. It will not do in a few sweeping words to re-assert an old dictum of the last century, and to condemn some of the greatest improvements of the time because they will not agree with it. Instead of one dictum, laissez faire, laissez passer, we must have at least one science, one new branch of the old political economy. Were time available I might go on to show that this is by no means the only new branch of the science needed. We need, for instance, a science of the money market, and of commercial fluctuations, which shall inquire why the world is all activity for a few years, and then all inactivity; why, in short, there are such tides in the affairs of men. But I am quite satisfied if I have pointed out the need and the probable rise of one new branch, which is only to be found briefly and imperfectly represented in the works of Mill or other economists.

The future of political economy is not likely to be such a blank as some of the speakers at the centennial dinner would lead us to suppose. I hope that the Political Economy Club may exist long enough to hold their second centennial celebration of the “Wealth of Nations,” and that then the disrupted fragments into which political economy seems now to be falling will have proved themselves the seeds of a new growth of beneficent sciences.

Source: The Fortnightly Review, Vol. 20, No. 129 (November 1, 1876), pp. 617-631.

Source:  University of Manchester Library. Rylands Collection, Jevons Family Papers. Jevons Album. (Image Number JRL023256tr).

Note: The photograph comes from a collection of photographs of Australia, taken or compiled by William Stanley Jevons during the 1850s. Between 1854-1859 Jevons was employed as assayer at the Sydney mint and also carried out detailed social surveys of the city’s slums.

Categories
Columbia Economists Methodology New School

Columbia. Wesley Clair Mitchell’s remarks at Conference on Methods in Philosophy and the Sciences, 1937

 

In brief remarks intended to give non-economists a sense of the major methodological schools of economics at a 1937 conference at the New School for Social Research, Columbia professor Wesley Clair Mitchell distinguishes (i) orthodox economics dedicated to the understanding of the “pecuniary logic” of an agent within a capitalist market environment, (ii) institutional economics dedicated to the understanding of the evolution of economic organization, and (iii) a new, yet unnamed, type of economic theory that is clearly recognizable as being “behavioral economics”.

____________________

Conference Program

CONFERENCE ON METHODS IN PHILOSOPHY AND THE SCIENCES

New School for Social Research
66 West 12th Street
New York City, N.Y.

Saturday, May 22 and Sunday, May 23, 1937

PROGRAM

Saturday, May 22

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

9:30 A.M. – 11:00 A.M – Registration, Room 24, Fee – $1.00

11:00 A.M. – 1:00 P.M. – First Session – Room 25

Chairman:  H. M. Kallen
Sidney Hook: The Current Philosophical Scene
John Dewey: A Possible Program for Libertarians and Experimentalists

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

2:30 – 4:00 P:M: – Second Session – Room 25

Brief statements on various departments of philosophy and the sciences: Their assumptions, methods, histories of the different schools, etc.

Ernest Nagel: The Position in LOGIC and METHODOLOGY
W.M. Malisoff: The Position in the PHYSICAL SCIENCES

DISCUSSION

4:00 – 5:30 P.M. – Second Session Continued – Room 25

S. E. Asch: The Position in PSYCHOLOGY
Wesley C. Mitchell: The Position in ECONOMICS

DISCUSSION

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

7:00 P.M. – DINNER, Gene’s 71 West 11th Street

Speakers: Bacchus, Dionysus, the Holy and other Spirits.
Appointment of Committees

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

Sunday, May 23

10:00 A.M. – 12 M. – Third Session, Room 25

Julius Lips: The Position in ANTHROPOLOGY
Meyer Schapiro: The Position in AESTHETICS
R. M. MacIver: The Position in SOCIOLOGY

DISCUSSION

12M. – 1:00 P.M. – Business Meeting

Election of Officers
Appointment of Permanent Committees
Unfinished Business
Adjournment

 

____________________

Handwritten Remark by Wesley Clair Mitchell
Economics

 

Conference on Methods in Philosophy and the Social Sciences

New School
May 22, 1937

Economics like Philosophy and the other Social Sciences is still in the stage of development marked by the existence of fairly distinct schools of thought, or as I like better to say Types of Theory.

These schools differ in method. But these differences in method arise from differences in the problems which are taken as the central concern of economics.

 

Orthodox economics concerns itself primarily with what I like to call pecuniary logic — what it is to the economic advantage of men to do under a capitalistic organization — and the ‘purer’ this theory becomes the more exclusive concentration on that problem becomes.

In dealing with pecuniary logic, the investigator employs the method of imaginary experimentation. That is, he sets up certain assumptions and seeks to think out what it is to the interest of men to do under the conditions supposed.

The theory is developed by varying these assumptions with reference to such matters as the factors in theory set which are allowed to change the length of the period considered in the problem, the degree of competition supposed, elasticities of demand, relations between unit costs and volume of output.

How far the conclusions apply to the actual world depends upon the character of the assumptions made. The correspondence between these assumptions and actual conditions is seldom investigated.

Hence the doubts about this type of theory are usually doubts, not about the correctness of the reasoning, but about how far they apply to the facts we wish to understand. May have uncertain ‘operational significance’.  Defence.—tool makers. Question about applicability not relevant.

This description applies less strictly to Marshall than to many of his pupils, to the later Austrians, and to mathematical economists.

 

Institutional economics concerns itself primarily with the evolution of economic organization.

To Veblen this meant study of the widely prevalent habits of thought.

To Commons it means study of social controls over induced action—primarily through the courts.

Methods employed combine ethnology or historical research with reasoning about how men with a certain set of habits ingrained in them by the social environment in which they have grown up and by the work they do will behave or how the social controls over induced behavior may be expected to work out.

Again there may be doubts about how far the reasoning concerning economic behavior applies to actual conditions.

 

A third type of economics seems to be developing though not represented as yet by systematic theoretical treatises.

It endeavors to learn by analytic studies of actual behavior how men conduct themselves. Its methods are closer kin to those of animal psychologists than to those of introspective psychologists.

Though these men show no reluctance to account for their observations by supposing that their subjects know the rules of the money-making and money-spending games. Here they go beyond outlook[?] of physical science— Supposes men have purposes: that they plan for future .

Large use of the mass observations afforded by statistics

Considerable emphasis upon method[?] analysis of these records.

Not confined to statistics.

Doubts here concern representative value [or volume?] of the data

Trustworthiness of the mathematical analysis.

Extent to which factors that are not recorded statistically may modify conclusions drawn. Work of this sort is primarily monographic. Since social phenomena are interdependent, the question concerning what is left out is highly important

Can’t be applied well except when mass observations are available.

Promises to develop in future because statistical observation is covering a wider range.

Danger of ‘mere fact finding’ Dewey. Yes, but the facts may have deep ‘operational’ significance. Relation to questions of policy.

 

Source: Columbia University Archives. W. C. Mitchell Collection. Box 3, Folder “5/22/37 A”.

Image Source: Wesley Clair Mitchell from Albert Arnold Sprague’s and Claudia C. Milstead’s Genealogical Website.

 

Categories
Economists Methodology New School

New School for Social Research. Conference on Mathematics and Social Science, 1958

 

While searching for traces of Jacob Marschak in the digitized archives on-line for the New School for Social Research, I came across the following press release about a one-day conference on mathematization of the social sciences that featured R. Duncan Luce, William S. Vickrey, Tjalling C. Koopmans and Jacob Marschak among others. Perhaps papers or notes from the conference can be located by a fellow historian of social sciences?

_______________________

Conference on “The State of Mathematization of the Social Sciences”
Press release from The New School for Social Research

THE NEW SCHOOL FOR SOCIAL RESEARCH.
66 West Twelfth Street, New York 11, New York

From: Agnes de Lima
Director of Information
Regon 5-2700

FOR RELEASE

May 21, 1958
MAILED May 21 to city editors of dailies

 

Mathematical methods in the social sciences—in psychology, sociology and economics—will be discussed by nine leading scholars at an all-day conference to be held at the New School for Social Research, Sunday, May 25. Scholars drawn from Columbia, Harvard, Princeton and Yale will address the conference which meets at 10:30 A.M. and again at 2:30 P.M. Dr. Henry Margenau, Eugene Higgins Professor of Natural History and Physics at Yale, will preside.

Dr. William Gruen, associate professor of philosophy at New York University, will introduce the speakers. He described the conference, which bears the rather formidable title, “The State of Mathematization of the Social Sciences,” as in the nature of a progress report on the application of the game theory, and related theoretical techniques developed by the late distinguished mathematical physicist John von Neumann of Princeton University. Much of the conference, he said, will deal with the extension of the line of research begun by the epoch-making work of Drs. Von Neumann and Oscar Morgenstern, also of Princeton, on “The Theory of Games and Economic Behavior.”

Speakers at the morning session include Robert R. Bush, associate professor of applied mathematics, New York School for Social Work, Columbia; R. Duncan Luce, lecturer, Department of Social Relations, Harvard; and William S. Vickrey, associate professor of economics, Columbia. Carl G. Hempel, professor of philosophy, Princeton, will comment.

In the afternoon session addresses will be made by Tjalling C. Koopmans, professor of economics, Yale; Jacob Marschak, professor of economics, Yale; Paul F. Lazarsfeld, professor of sociology and chairman of the Department of Sociology, Columbia. Ernest Nagel, John Dewey Professor of Philosophy, Columbia, and Orville G. Brim, Russell Sage Foundation, will comment.

The meeting is sponsored by the Conference on Methods in Philosophy and the Sciences organized in 1957 by a group of top-ranking scholars from leading universities. This is the 43rd [sic, probably “3rd”] semi-annual gathering at the New School.

Dr. Margenau is chairman of the conference and Dr. Gruen is secretary-treasurer. Dr. Horace M. Kallen, research professor in social philosophy and professor emeritus of the Graduate Faculty of Political and Social Science of the New School, is honorary president.

 

Note to Editor: While next Sunday’s Conference on Methods in Philosophy and the Sciences is a scholar’s conference and some of the papers will be technical in nature your reporter can we believe gain some highly interesting material on the light thrown on human motivation and behavior by the application of mathematical methods in the fields of psychology, sociology and economics. Leading corporations in the country in recognition of this fact are increasingly employing mathematicians on their staffs. We suggest that your reporter get in touch with Dr. William Gruen at the conference.

Above “Note to Ed” added to copies of release for NY Times and Herald Trib.

 

Source: New School for Social Research (New York, N.Y.: 1919-1997). Announcement of a conference “The State of Mathematization of the Social Sciences“. May 21 1958. New School press release collection. New School Archives and Special Collections Digital Archive. Web. 07 Mar 2019.

Image Source: Exterior of 66 West 12th Street Building of The New School. 1930 – 1960. New School photograph collection; Buildings and campus (NS040101.SII). New School Archives and Special Collections Digital Archive. Web. 07 Mar 2019.

 

Categories
Exam Questions Harvard Methodology

Harvard. Final Exam for Scope and Method of Economics. Taussig, 1896.

 

Frank Taussig returned from a sabbatical to teach a course on the scope and method(s) of economics at Harvard during the second term of 1895-96. The following years his colleague, the economic historian William Ashley, taught the course.

The enrollment figures and final examination questions for Taussig’s course are provided below.

____________________

COURSE ANNOUNCEMENT

[Economics] 13hf. Scope and Method in Economic Theory and Investigation. Half-course. Wed., Fri., and (at the pleasure of the instructor) Mon., at 1.30 (second half-year). Professor Taussig.

Source: The Harvard University Catalogue, 1895-96,p. 100.

 

COURSE ENROLLMENT

[Economics] 132. Professor Taussig.—Scope and Method in Economic Theory and Investigation. hf. 2 hours, 2d half-year.

Total 14: 11 Graduates, 3 Seniors.

 

Source: Harvard University. Report of the President of Harvard College, 1895-1896, p. 63.

 

1895-96
ECONOMICS 13.
[Final examination]

  1. Compare Wagner’s enumeration of the problems within the scope of economic science with Keynes’s; and consider what doubts or objections there may be in regard to any of the problems mentioned by either writer.
  2. Explain and examine critically one of the following passages in Wagner:

Section 63 (pp. 158-163).
Section 70 (pp. 180-182).

  1. Illustrate the mode in which use is advantageously made of the deductive and the inductive method in regard to two of the following topics:

the causes which determine the general range of prices;
the prospects of socialism;
the prospects of cooperation.

  1. What peculiarities and difficulties appear for economic science in the choice of terminology and in definition? Illustrate.
  2. Is there ground for saying that the economic history of very recent times is of greater value for economic theory than the economic history of remote periods?
  3. What do you conceive to be the position in regard to method in economics of Ricardo? J.S. Mill? Roscher? Schmoller?

 

Source: Harvard University Archives. Prof. F. W. Taussig Examination Papers in Economics, 1882-1935, (HUC 7882), p. 55.

Image Source: Harvard Portfolio, vol. VI, 1895 .